Return To HD Support Information Website
Genetic Information and the Family
by Bartha Maria Knoppers
Posted January 18, 2002 · Issue 118 HMS Beagle http://news.bmn.com/hmsbeagle/118/notes/feature1
Abstract
Nowhere are the principles of autonomy and privacy more frequently underscored
than in the context of modern human genetics. Fear of
untoward socioeconomic
and psychosocial consequences of genetic knowledge has
reinforced the need for
medical confidentiality. However, genetic information
is necessarily familial and the
needs and interests of other family members cannot be
ignored. The past decade
has witnessed a gradual move away from the status quo
position of absolute
confidentiality, to an intermediary position of it being
the duty of the patient, to a
position making it ethically permissible for the physician to
warn in certain limited
circumstances. Founded on the principle of mutuality, this last
position will
revolutionize not only the physician-patient relationship but
also the modern,
nuclear family.
At a moment in history when globalization, pandemics, and the increasing
divide between rich and poor constitute humanity's major preoccupations,
what role is left for individuals, families and communities?
I would maintain that although confronting these staggering challenges remains a priority, we must not neglect the
ultimate source of change, that of each citizen within his and her family and community. Although rarely seen as a tool
for social change or for greater equity in genomics, I would suggest that the availability of human genetic information
will revolutionize not only the physician-patient relationship but also the social fabric of the modern nuclear family.
Modern human genetics might well spur the recreation of the genealogical family and thus foster new obligations based
on mutuality and not just on individual autonomy.
Nevertheless, fear of untoward socioeconomic and psychosocial consequences of genetic knowledge has
spawned a decade of statements and guidelines underscoring the need to respect individual autonomy. Indeed, the rights
to privacy, to medical confidentiality, and to what some have called "genetic ignorance" [1-3] have been reinforced
by the genetic revolution. This is all the more paradoxical considering that genetic information is familial. For that
reason, I argue that although the decision to be tested must be the sole perogative of the autonomous individual, due
consideration should be given to the needs and interests of other family members.
To that end, I propose that
we begin to develop the principle of mutuality to promote the interests of others. This principle maintains the risk sharing
and risk spreading. In the context of genetic research, testing, and information, how can it be interpreted? It could
mean: (1) maintaining the status quo - that is, the principle of medical confidentiality and individual autonomy where
the risks are minimal, or (2) an intermediary position of doing no harm or preventing harm through the promotion of
an ethical duty on the part of the patient to warn at-risk relatives, or (3) through making it ethically permissible for
physicians to warn at-risk relatives when certain conditions are present.
The Status Quo Position
Since 1990, coinciding with the appearance of the first statements
on the ethical implications of genetic testing, there has been an ethical and legal reinforcement of the duty of medical
confidentiality. In the absence of a legislative exception, the maintenance of such secrecy is not only sacrosanct but
is seen as essential to ensure the trust inherent in relationships of a fiduciary nature.
Even this position does
not go so far as to advocate total abstinence of communication. It limits itself, however, to attempting to persuade the
patient to warn at-risk relatives even where the patient insists on full confidentiality [4]. Indeed, the relatives
are in no worse position with the absence of warning because, strictly speaking, the patient does not "cause" the
genetic risk.
The patient might also be best situated to evaluate whether such at-risk relatives would want to
know. This position, however, presumes that modern families are functional, live in close proximity and are aware of each
other's values and lifestyle preferences.
Furthermore, this status quo position totally ignores the unique character
of genetic information and shields individualism (however ill- or well-motivated) from any form of familial or communal
scrutiny. It is still the current norm, although increasingly attenuated by an intermediary position.
The Intermediary Position
The intermediary position places a positive duty on the physician
not only to try to persuade the patient to communicate with at-risk blood relatives but also to warn patients of its
potential familial implications before taking a genetic test. Indeed, this approach is strengthened in those countries,
mainly those of the Napoleonic tradition, in which vestiges of this "duty to rescue" remain. Thus, the principle of
to do no harm, together with the duty to rescue, would hold that there is an ethical duty on the patient to warn his/her
relatives. Moreover, where patients do not want to exercise this ethical duty, the physician may do so with the patient's
consent [5].
Although this approach lacks the certainty and clarity of the status
quo position, it goes further in recognizing that the health and welfare of others might be at stake. Together with
encouragement from the physician, it might well be sufficient in close families but, at best, it would be arbitrary
and uneven in its exercise. Finally, owing to its discretionary nature, it could also become a tool of revenge in dysfunctional
families. Absent some cultural or religious imperative, in reality, it might go no further than the status quo position.
Hence, the past five years have witnessed a move away from both the status quo and the intermediary positions to that
of mutuality.
The Position of Mutuality
In this way, a serious burden on others can be avoided. This position, however, in no way advocates
a legal duty to warn. For now such ethical "permission" will at a minimum serve as a defence in a possible suit for
breach of confidentiality [6]. Nevertheless, it seconds the position that between the human genome at the collective level
being considered the common heritage of humanity and at the personal level as being unique and belonging to the individual,
the information it contains is also familial. The adoption of this translation of the principle of mutuality with
respect to genetic information will reinforce what the World Health Organizaton (WHO) has maintained with regard to DNA
samples which it sees as subject to familial control [7].
In the situation of repeated refusal by the patient, four conditions must be met before it is seen as
ethically permissible for the physician to breach medical confidentiality: (1) the condition in question must be serious
with (2) a high probability of occurrence, (3) in an identifiable blood relative(s) and (4) prevention or treatment
must be available.
In this way, a serious burden on others can be avoided. This position, however, in no way advocates a legal duty to
warn. For now such ethical "permission" will at a minimum serve as a defence in a possible suit for breach of confidentiality
[6]. Nevertheless, it seconds the position that between the human genome at the collective level being considered the
common heritage of humanity and at the personal level as being unique and belonging to the individual, the information
it contains is also familial. The adoption of this translation of the principle of mutuality with respect to genetic
information will reinforce what the World Health Organizaton (WHO) has maintained with regard to DNA samples which it
sees as subject to familial control [7].
In short, the very nature of genetic information, as both individual and universal, now mandates its treatment as familial.
The future availability of inexpensive multiplex testing might allow routine individual knowledge of thousands of
mutations and so lessen the need to warn at-risk relatives. However, at present, the acceptance of the principle of mutuality in
the sharing of information in families (and hopefully one day in whole communities at risk), serves to reinforce the notion
that we are literally our brothers' keeper.
Finally, the sharing of genetic information could also serve to "normalize" it. If so, we can one day end the stigmatization
and discrimination that is currently associated with genetic information and integrate it into modern medicine, as normal
medical information in more caring and sharing families.
See Source: HMS Beagle for the referenced links in article http://news.bmn.com/hmsbeagle/118/notes/feature1
|